The Ernest Gellner Memorial Lecture
Memory and modernity: reflections on Ernest Gellner's theory of nationalism
by Anthony D. Smith
European Institute, London School of Economics and Political Science, Houghton St, London WC2A 2AE
This is a sad and strange occasion. I have been asked to stand in the place
where my teacher, Ernest Gellner, was to stand today and to continue an
unfinished dialogue which we have been conducting for much of our
scholarly lives. I have been asked to speak to you about Ernest's theory of
nationalism, the great issue of the modern world with which he grappled all
his life and to which he made so unique and profound a contribution.
Though I had heard Ernest lecture in 1964 and 1965, it was only when he
agreed to supervise my Ph.D. thesis in 1966 that I came into close contact
with him on a regular basis. Since that time, Ernest has been in my thoughts
as a teacher and scholar, and above all as a pioneer of the sociological study
of our common passionate interest in nationalism. (And in our last
meetings, both of us shared the hope of seeing a sister Institute dedicated to
the study of nationalism being created at LSE, similar to that which Ernest
directed at the Central European University in Prague. But that hope seems
unlikely to be realised).
Though I had read Words and Things at Oxford, my first real encounter
with Ernest's thought was with his second book, Thought and Change
(1964), especially the chapter on nationalism. This chapter has largely set
the terms of subsequent debate in the field. From this encounter, and my
subsequent work under Ernest's supervision, I took away four fundamental
lessons in the study of nationalism.
The first was the centrality of nationalism for an understanding of the
modern world. The fact that Ernest took up the issues of nationalism in the
1960s and that he kept returning to them, when most social scientists were
interested in Marxism, functionalism, phenomenology, indeed everything
but nationalism, and the fact that he established a Centre for the Study of
Nationalism in Prague devoted to research and latterly teaching in this field,
demonstrates how thoroughly he appreciated the power, ubiquity and
durability of nationalism.
The second lesson that I learnt from Ernest was the need to appreciate
the sheer complexity, the protean elusiveness, of the phenomena that were
gathered together under the rubric of 'nationalism'. This is why he insisted
on comparative analysis, and on the need to formulate typologies that do
justice to the complexities of nationalism.
A third lesson was the sociological reality of nations and nationalism.
Unlike many latterday scholars for whom the nation is a cultural artefact
and nationalism a discourse, Ernest insisted on the structural embeddedness
of nations and nationalism. Hence, the need, as he saw it, to use sociological
concepts and methods to provide an understanding of this most complex of
phenomena. This meant of course jettisoning nationalism's own account of
itself, as an awakening of the slumbering but primordial nation through the
kiss of nationalist Prince Charmings; and, instead, grasping nationalism as
the necessary outcome of a particular kind of social structure and culture.
The final lesson was the hardest, the one on which I have stumbled most.
Nations as well as nationalisms, Ernest argued, are wholly modern. They
are not only recent, dating from the period of the French Revolution or a
bit earlier, they are also novel, the products of 'modernity' that whole
nexus of processes that went into the making of the West over the last four
centuries, including capitalism, industrialism, urbanisation, the bureaucratic
state and secularisation.
It was this final lesson that was at issue in our last encounter at Warwick,
when, at the invitation of Edward Mortimer and the university, Ernest and
I debated the origins and functions of nationalism. That debate, just twelve
days before his tragically early death, was entitled: 'The nation: real or
imagined?' But since we both agreed that nations, like buildings or works of
art, are created - albeit over generations - and are therefore both real and
imagined, the question became the different but perhaps more important
one of the relationship between nations and their putative pasts. It is, after
all, difficult to see how a purely cultural artefact could inspire the loyalty
and self-sacrifice of countless people. On the other hand, the primordialist
picture of natural nations, of nations inscribed in the natural order, was
equally unacceptable. So the question then became: where do nations come
from?
Do nations have navels?
Or, in Ernest's words, 'Do nations have navels'?
This question was the title that Ernest gave me for this Nations and
Nationalism lecture, as we stood on the platform in Coventry after the
Warwick debate. Hence my problem, and my title. Fortunately, Warwick
University kindly supplied me with a transcript of Ernest's reply to my
opening statement in that debate. Let me quote the bit about national
navels, on which he hoped to elaborate. Speaking of the dividing line
between modernists and primordialists, Ernest asked for the kind of
evidence that would decide whether nations had pasts that matter, or
whether the world and nations with them was created about the end of the
eighteenth century, 'and nothing before that makes the slightest difference
to the issues we face'. 'Was mankind', he asked, 'the creator of Adam and
did it slowly evolve?' The evidence that was debated at the time this issue
was alive revolved around the question: did Adam have or did he not have a navel? Now, it's a very crucial question, you
see. No, no you may fall about laughing, but obviously if Adam was created by God
at a certain date, let's say 4,003 BC, obviously I mean it's a prima facie first reaction
that he didn't have a navel, so to say, because Adam did not go through the process
by which people acquire navels. Therefore we do know what will decide whether the
world is very old and mankind evolved or whether the world was created about
6,000 years ago. Namely, all we need to know is whether Adam had a navel or not.
The question I'm going to address myself to of course is do nations have navels or
do they not?
My main case for modernism that I'm trying to highlight in this debate, is that on
the whole the ethnic, the cultural national community, which is such an important
part of Anthony's case, is rather like the navel. Some nations have it and some
don't, and in any case, it's inessential (Gellner 1995, 1-2). What in a way Anthony is
saying is that he is anti-creationist and we have this plethora of navels and they are
essential, as he said, and this I think is the crux of the case between him and me.
In my opening statement at Warwick, I had argued that the modernist
standpoint which Ernest embraced - the idea that nations are products of
modernisation and could not have existed before the advent of modernity -
told only half the story (Smith 1995b)
Well, if it tells half the story [Ernest quipped], that is for me enough, because it
means that the additional bits of the story in the other half are redundant. He may
not have meant it this way, but if the modernist theory accounts for half or 60% or
40% or 30% of the nations, this is good for me. (Ibid., 2)
Well, as Ernest knew, I certainly didn't mean it that way. But, from his
standpoint, it would actually suffice if there were just one case of a nation
being accounted for by modernism, for modernism to be true. And he
produced his case: the Estonians. This is what he had to say about them:
At the beginning of the nineteenth century they didn't even have a name for
themselves. They were just referred to as people who lived on the land, as opposed
to German or Swedish burghers and aristocrats and Russian administrators. They
had no ethnonym. They were just a category without any ethnic self-consciousness.
Since then they've been brilliantly successful in creating a vibrant culture. (Ibid., 2)
And he went on to praise this 'very vital and vibrant culture', which is so
vividly displayed in the Ethnographic Museum in Tartu with its 100,000
objects, one for every 10 Estonians, claiming that it was created by 'the kind
of modernist process which I then generalise for nationalism and nations in
general'. And Ernest returned to the Estonians, at the end of his opening
statement, when he tried to list the factors that may help us to predict which
potential nations or cultural categories will assert themselves, a question I
had posed in my opening statement: Now obviously it does matter to predict which nations will assert themselves, which
potential nations, which cultural categories will assert themselves and which will not.
I would say it is inherent in the situation that you cannot tell. You can indicate
certain factors. Size is an obvious one, very small cultural groups give up. Continuity
is another one, but not an essential one. Some diasporic communities have very
effectively asserted themselves. Size, continuity, existence of symbolism, are impor-
tant, but again the Estonians created nationalism ex nihilo in the course of the
nineteenth century. (Ibid., 3)
I could quibble here, and say that the issue was not whether the
Estonians created nationalism ex nihilo in the nineteenth century, but
whether the Estonian nation was created by the Estonian nationalists ex
nihilo. And while we would both agree that Estonian nationalism, indeed
any nationalism, was modern, where Ernest and I would differ is whether
the nations that nationalism creates are wholly modern creations ex nihilo.
Ernest returned to this question, when he disagreed with my reading of the
classical legacy of modern Greece, but admitted that there is some continuity with Byzantium or at any rate with the clerical organisation
left behind by Byzantium certainly, but sometimes there is and sometimes there isn't
[continuity]. So I would say in general there is a certain amount of navel about, but
not everywhere and on the whole it's not important. It's not like the cycles of
respiration, blood circulation or food digestion which Adam would have to have in
order to live at the moment of creation. (Ibid., 3)
Now here lies the rub. If we pursue the analogy, we recall that God created
Adam, fashioning his body and then breathing life into it. Not even the
most megalomaniac nationalist has claimed quite that power. They have, of
course, seen themselves as awakeners; but the body of the nation merely
slumbered, it was not without life. Should we confer on nationalists that
divine power, to create ex nihilo?
Of course, Ernest wants to confer that power through nationalism
ultimately on modernity, on the growth society, on industrialism and its
cultural prerequisites. For Ernest, the genealogy of the nation is located in
the requirements of modernity, not the heritage of pre-modern pasts. Ernest
is claiming that nations have no parents, no pedigree, except the needs of
modern society. Those needs can only be met by a mass, public, literate,
specialised and academy-supervised culture, a 'high culture', preferably in a
specific language which allows context-free communication. A 'high culture'
is the only cement for a modern, mobile, industrial society; and this is the
only kind of society open to us today.
For Ernest, the world was irreversibly transformed by a cluster of
economic and scientific changes since the seventeenth century. Traditional
agro-literate societies were increasingly replaced by growth-oriented, mobile,
industrial societies. The rise of high cultures and nations is a consequence of
the mobility and anonymity of modern society and of the semantic, non-
physical nature of modern work. Today what really matters is not kingship
or land or faith, but education into and membership of a high culture
community, that is, a nation (Gellner 1983, ch. 2).
So, just as Pallas Athene sprang fully armed from the head of Zeus,
without parents, so nations emerged fully-fledged from the requirements of
modernity. If nations did have navels, they were purely ornamental.
But, can we derive nations tout court from the needs of modernity? To
be fair, it isn't modernity that directly creates nations. To quote Ernest's
original formulation: '[Nationalism] invents nations where they do not exist,
- but it does need some preexisting differentiating marks to work on, even
if ... these are purely negative' (Gellner 1964, 168). The same sequence is
restated in his later book: "It is nationalism which engenders nations, and not the other way round." Admittedly, nationalism uses the preexisting, historically inherited proliferation of cultures or cultural wealth, though it uses them very selectively and it most often transforms them radically. Dead languages can be revived, traditions invented, quite fictitious pristine purities restored. But this culturally creative, fanciful, positively inventive
aspect of nationalist ardour ought not to allow anyone to conclude, erroneously,
that nationalism is a contingent, artificial, ideological invention ... (Gellner 1983,
55-56)
This is a crucial passage, but it is by no means an isolated one.
Throughout his writings on nationalism, Ernest keeps returning to the idea
that nationalisms frequently make use of the past, albeit very selectively.
This reveals an ambivalence at the heart of his theory, one highlighted by
the word 'admittedly' in the passage I have just quoted. It is this
ambivalence that I wish to explore, because here, I believe, lies the main
limitation of all 'modernist' theories of nationalism, including Ernest's. I
want to examine this ambivalence under three headings: the parentage or
genealogy of nations, the question of cultural continuity and transforma-
tion, and the role of collective memory.
The genealogy of nations
As far as the genealogy of nations is concerned, Ernest is saying two things.
Nations are navel-less, they don't have parents; and even if they did, it's
irrelevant. Nations begin de novo, in a brave new industrial world.
One might start by asking which of these positions Ernest really claims.
If some nations had navels, they had ancestors. We could then try to
compare the navel-less, ancestor-less nations with the nations that had
navels and ancestors, to see how each class of nations was faring. That is an
interesting empirical question. But, if having ancestors is a priori irrelevant,
then why should even some nationalisms make use of 'their' pasts? Note, it
is not any past. For my nation, your past will not do. It has to be 'my' past,
or pasts, or more usually, some of my pasts. But why return to the past at
all? If the past is irrelevant to the needs of a modern society, then why does
any nationalism bother to return to some sort of 'past'? Is this just a
delusion, a matter of false consciousness? That is a position Ernest would, I
believe, strongly deny, but he does not really explore the issue.
The other answer often given to this question is that elites, or people in
general, have to return to tradition and ancestry to legitimate the new type
of industrial-capitalist society and control the changes it must undergo. But
that only begs the question as to why elites or people in general feel the
need to refer back to 'their' ancestral traditions, or 'invent' ones that are
aligned with these older traditions. Can it be because they are still quite
powerful, and many people still operate in terms of these traditions,
however irrelevant they may seem to some clites and to the theorist of
modernity? In other words, many people appear not only to believe they
have navels; they believe in the reality of the situation which gave them
navels, and which their navels symbolise. In short, they believe they have
collective parents, and these parents are in important ways relevant to their
present situation (Matossian 1962; Hobsbawm and Ranger 1983, Introduc-
tion and ch. 7).
This belief is not entirely unfounded. Historically, the members of a
community can point to a considerable amount of evidence to support their
belief in the genealogy of nations. They can refer to documents and artefacts
which bear out their belief that many present-day industrial or industria-
lising societies from England and France to Russia and Poland, from Japan
and Korea to America and Mexico, are closely related to, indeed grew out
of, past communities with which they identify. Members can point to the
fact that, despite the many transformations they have undergone, their
nations continue to share with past communities such features as a proper
name, a rough territory, a language, some artistic styles, sets of myths and
symbols, traditions of heroes and heroines, memories of golden ages, and
the like. In other words, they conceive of their nation, despite all these
changes, as 'stemming from' older communities of historic culture with
whom they share myths of descent and common memories, including links
with a homeland (cf. Johnson 1992).
We do not have to accept the ideology of nationalism itself, with its
romantic belief in the awakening of the nation, its mission and destiny, to
realise that we cannot fully grasp the rise and character of so many modern
nations unless we explore their historical antecedents, and the continuing
influence of those antecedents in the modern epoch. Ernest's modernism
tells us how a modern nation operates, indeed must operate, in the modern,
industrial age. But it cannot tell us which nations will emerge where, and
why these nations rather than others.
To return to an example which Ernest used in the Warwick debate:
modern Israel, he argued, is furnished with all the cultural equipment
needed in the modern world: a literate, mass public education system, a
common modernised language, a modern system of communications and
legal system, in short, a 'high culture' of the kind required by the mobile,
anonymous society which industrialism creates. In a state like Israel, where
immigrants from over seventy lands and many cultures have been
ingathered, this sort of standardised, public, unifying, 'high culture' is all
the more necessary. To cope with the challenges of modernity, which is
what any society must do if it is to survive today, you require a 'high
culture'. In the modern world, the culture and religion of the past is at best
irrelevant, at worst an impediment (cf. Friedmann 1967; Vital 1990, chs.
5-6).
But equally, in my view, this example demonstrates that we cannot hope
to explain the rise and character of modern nations solely in terms of the
requirements of modernity. Even that arch-modernist Theodor Herzl
conceived of Israel as a haven for an ancient diaspora people, a Judenslaat,
a state of and for unassimilable Jews, taking up where the last independent
Jewish state, the Hasmonean state, had left off, in Zion. It was this
ultimately religious and political vision, rather than the needs of modernity,
that inspired and mobilised many diaspora Jews to become Zionists and
take the arduous road to Palestine; and it was a vision that assumed a
genealogy and an ancient pedigree and name for a nation-to-be, one that
addressed, as does every nationalism, a designated and particular 'people'.
To assert, with another modernist, Erie Hobsbawm, that there is simply no
connection between the age-old Jewish yearnings and pilgrimages to Zion
and the modern ingathering of Jewish exiles into Palestine, is to miss, not
only the element of ethnic ascription, but also the whole aspect of popular
motivation and collective self-understanding which is essential to the success
of any nationalism. This is what I meant when I argued that modernism can
tell us only half the story. It tells us in general why there have to be nations
and nationalism in the modern world; it does not tell us what those nations
will be, or where they will emerge, or. why so many people are prepared to
die for them. Nor does it tell us much about the character of particular
nationalisms, whom they address, and whether they are religious or secular,
conservative or radical, civic or ethnic - issues that are vital both for the
participants and their victims, and for a scholarly understanding of nations
and nationalism (Hobsbawm 1990, ch. 1; Wistrich 1995).
I am suggesting, then, that to understand modern nations and nation-
alism, we have to explore not only the processes and requirements of
modernity, but also the genealogies of nations. In fact, we have to explore
the impact of the processes of modernisation on those genealogies, and the
way in which they give rise to selections and transformations by each
generation of preexisting ethnic ties and of the ethnic traditions they have
inherited.
Now, we may admit that in the case of the nations I have cited, it makes
sense to explore their genealogies. But, what of modern nations that have
lost their parents or never had them, or are not quite sure who their parents
were? This poses considerable problems for nationalists attempting to create
nations. It is certainly one reason for the enormous popularity of the
Kalevala with the Finns, and the Kalevipoeg with the Estonians. (Yes, the
Estonians did have a navel, after all. As a leading historian of Estonia,
Toivo Raun, writing of the Estonian national revival of the 1860s, put it:
'Among the Estonian population, the importance of Kalevipoeg was not so
much literary - it took decades to reach a wide audience - as it was
symbolic, affirming the historical existence of the Estonian nation' (Raun
1987, 56, 76; cf. Branch 1985, Introduction).)
Both epics traced the descent of the Finns and Estonians to Iron Age
culture-communities, and thereby provided these dispossessed and subject
peoples with a sense of their dignity through native ancestry and an
ancient and heroic ethnic past. In this way, they confirmed the worldwide
belief in the virtues of national geneologies. To dismiss this by attributing
it to the ubiquitous influence of nationalism again begs the question of
why so many people have been mobilised on the basis of this particular
belief in the genealogy of nations. Besides, nationalists have usually
managed to find some historical antecedents for their nations-to-be, albeit
often embellished and exaggerated, and this suggests that there are
mechanisms at work which ensure some connection and even continuity
between the modern nation and one or more pasts. To two of these
mechanisms I now turn.
Cultural change and continuity
The first lies in the field of culture, and it provides us with a second focus
for exploring the ambivalence in Ernest's and other versions of modernism.
For Ernest, modernity introduces a radical cultural break. This has two
aspects. The first is underlined in the theorem which underpins his early
formulation of modernism. That theorem states that in pre-modern
societies, culture reinforces structure, whereas in modern societies, culture
replaces structure. By this Ernest meant that kinship roles organised social
life in simple, traditional societies, and symbols, myths, traditions and codes
reinforced and expressed that kinship structure. Modern society, with the
possible exception of bureaucracy, has no such structure. Instead, it has a
common culture. In the polyglot, anonymous city, where most encounters
are ephemeral, people can only relate to each other through context-free
communication. This requires a common culture in preferably a common
language. The precondition of membership in such a society and of
citizenship in the state is literacy. Today, by necessity, 'we are all clerks'
(Gellner 1964, ch. 7).
In a later article and in his Nations and Nationalism, Ernest focused more
upon the changed nature of work and the generic training required for a
niobile, industrial society. To train a mobile workforce and citizenry to
inaster the techniques of semantic work, modern societies require a new
kind of education system. For this, Ernest coined the term lexo-socialisa-
tion'. In the old, agro-literate society, rote learning at one's mother's knee
or in the village school sufficed. In a modern, industrialising or industrial
society, external, state-imposed, standardised, mass schooling was needed to
create the literate and technically sophisticated workforce, necessary to man
the industrial machine. And the teachers, too, had to be specialised
educational personnel, able to service the new literate 'high culture' which
characterises and defines modern nations (Geliner 1973; 1982; 1983, ch. 3;
cf. also 1994, ch. 3).
This concept of a 'high culture' became the key to Ernest's later theory of
nationalism. In an interesting section of Nations and Nationalism, Ernest
contrasts the 'high' culture of modern societies with the 'low' cultures of
agro-literate societies. A 'high' culture, as we have seen, is a literate,
sophisticated culture, serviced by specialised educational personnel and
taught formally in mass, public, standardised and academy-supervised
institutions of learning. It is a highly cultivated or 'garden' culture. A 'low'
culture, by contrast, is wild, spontaneous, undirected and unsupervised.
These are the cultures that readily spring up, unbidden, in societies where
the great mass of the population are food-producers servicing the needs of
tiny specialised elites - clerisies, aristocracies, merchants and the like - who
are almost completely cut off socially and culturally from the peasant
masses. In such a society, there is neither need nor room for nations and
nationalisms, since the many 'low' cultures of the peasants are local and
,almost invisible'. Thus, in agro-literate societies, in Ernest's words: 'Culture
tends to be branded either horizontally (by social caste), or vertically, to
define very small local communities' (Gellner 1983, 16-17).
Now, for Ernest, all these 'low' cultures are doomed. They are cut off,
like so many umbilical cords, because they are simply irrelevant in an
impersonal, mobile modern society. If they are remembered at all, it is only
through some symbols, in the same way that navels remind us of our
origins. Nationalism, Ernest claims, is basically a product of modernity. It
is, he says,
essentially, the general imposition of a high culture on society, where previously low
Cultures had taken up the lives of the majority, and in some cases the totality, of the
Population ... it is the establishment of an anonymous, impersonal society, with
mutually substitutable atomized individuals, held together above all by a shared
Culture of this kind, in place of a previous complex structure of local groups,
sustained by folk cultures reproduced locally and idiosyncratically by the micro-
groups themselves. That is what really happens. (Gellner 1983, 57)
Nothing could be clearer. The many, old 'low' cultures vanish. They are
replaced by a single, new 'high' culture, or 'nation'. This is the true meaning
of nationalism.
But there are two problems here, of which Ernest was well aware. Some
'low' cultures are not severed. Instead, they become 'high' cultures. The
Finns and the Estonians clearly fall into this category, as do many of the
cultures of the other smaller, subject peoples of Eastern Europe and the
former Soviet Union. The other problem is that certain old elite cultures
become 'high' cultures. The literary cultures of the Jews, the Armenians and
the Greeks clearly fall under this heading, as do several of the cultures of
Western peoples like the Catalans, Scots and French. Awareness of the
difficulties posed for modernism by both these problems is an important
source of its ambivalence (Gellner 1994, 37-44).
How do 'low' cultures become 'high' cultures? Why does Estonian win
out over German, Swedish and Russian cultures in Estonia, and Finnish
over Swedish and Russian cultures in Finland? Both these cultures were
local, popular, largely confined to the peasants, at least at first. Why do
these 'Ruritanians' become conscious of their local folk cultures and seek to
turn what were 'low' cultures into 'high' ones for the nation-to-be?
Or were they really such 'low' cultures? And is the contrast between 'low'
and 'high' cultures as sharp as Ernest alleges? In the case of Estonia, we
know of Estonian language religious texts during the Reformation; and
certainly by the seventeenth century, with the establishment of the
University of Tartu and later Forselius' school system, the basis of a literate
Estonian culture emerged a century and a half before the arrival of the
Romantic movement in the Baltic states in the mid-nineteenth century.
True, Germans and Swedes made the running, but a native Estonian poem
of 1708 lamenting the miseries of the Great Northern War between Peter
the Great and the Swedes, fought over Estonian lands, reveals a growing
Estonian consciousness. Moreover, written Estonian can even be found in
the thirteenth century Chronicle of Henry of Livonia recording the German
conquest of Estonia in the face of much resistance. All this suggests that the
transition to an Estonian 'high' culture was much more gradual and long-
drawn-out than a modernist account would suggest (Raun 1987, 57, 76).
If this is the case with a so-called 'low' culture such as the Estonian, it is
likely to prove even more true of old, literate, specialist-supported and
therefore 'high' cultures like those of the French, the Arabs, the Jews and
the Greeks. True, the languages and cultures of these peoples had to be
1modernised' to cope with modern conditions: they had to be simplified,
standardised, secularised and expanded to cover all sorts of undreamt-of
phenomena and novel concepts, and embrace all classes and regions of the
nation-to-be. But the old 'high' caste-literate cultures were not scrapped and
replaced; they were adapted, purified, enlarged and diffused, often through
self-conscious cultural reformist movements. Sometimes, as in modern
Greece, this involved a measure of compromise with its pasts, between a
popular Byzantine Orthodox heritage and a classicising Athenian language
and culture. In this case, the recovery of ancient Greek texts and sculptures
did create considerable preoccupation with Periclean Athens among the
C,reek-speaking intelligentsia, but it had constantly to compete with the
more popular memories of Byzantium carried by an Orthodox liturgy and
congregation (Frazee 1969; but cf. Kitromilides 1989).
What 1 am arguing here is that most modern languages and cultures are
not 'invented': they are connected to, and often continuous with, much
older cultures which the modernising nationalists adapt and standardise. By
Ernest's criteria, many of these older languages and cultures were 'high'
cultures. But, even where they were 'low' (or 'lower'), spontaneous, popular
cultures, they could become the basis for a subsequent 'high culture'. Ernest
hints at this when he speaks of Ruritanians in the metropolis of
megalomania who, faced with the problems of labour migration and
bureaucracy, soon come to understand the difference between dealing with a
co-national, 'one understanding and sympathising with their culture, and
someone hostile to it. This very concrete experience taught them to be
aware of their culture, and to love it (or, indeed, to wish to be rid of it).' In
other words, it is the old 'low' culture to which they cling, or not, as the
case may be. And it is the old 'low' culture which, far from being cut off
and thrown away, will soon become the modern 'high' taught culture, albeit
for several hundred thousands or millions of people (Gellner 1983, 61).
There are many examples of this cultural connectedness and continuity
amid change, and we need to remind ourselves that cultural continuity is
not the same as cultural fixity. Take the realm of language development.
The English and French languages evolved over many centuries, with
several admixtures of other languages, yet we can trace lines of development
which reveal their underlying continuity. Alternatively, there is a conscious
reform of language and culture, as occurred with the Turkic languages
under the impulse of the jadid educational movement of Ismail Bey
Gasprinski, or with Hebrew through the modernising reforms of Eliezer
Ben-Yehudah. In the latter case, the differences between biblical and
modern Hebrew are considerable; yet modern Hebrew is clearly based upon,
and developed from, biblical Hebrew (Zenkovsky 1953; Fishman 1968;
Rickard 1974; Edwards 1985).
In terms of names, territorial attachments and myths of origin, too, there
are striking connections and continuities, despite changes of cultural
contents over time. This is especially true of island cultures like Japan, with
its relative continuity of territory, identity and origin myths. But it can also
be found in mixed cultures like that of Mexico, whose modern cultural
nationalists have sought to recover and reappropriate some aspects of the
pre-Colombian, mainly Aztec, past. Of course, it can be argued that the
very need to recover the past is evidence for discontinuity. There certainly
had been discontinuity, especially after Hernan Cortes' invasion. But,
among the many indigenous ethnies of Mexico, the old cultures still live in
varying degrees and guises, to be used as partial models and disseminated
through the mass, public education system to the mestizo majority (Franco
1970; Lehmann 1982; Florescano 1992).
Collective memory and modern nations
This leads us directly to the final focus of modernist ambivalence, namely,
the part played by collective memory in the formation of nations.
Collective memories form another major link with an ethnic past or
pasts. Ernest was very conscious of the role of memory in creating nations,
if only because, like Renan, he emphasised the importance of national
amnesia and getting one's history wrong for the maintenance of national
solidarity. But there was no systematic attempt in his work to deal with the
problems posed by shared memories of a collective past (Gellner 1982).
For Renan, memories were constitutive of the nation. The nation is built
on shared memories of joy and suffering, and above all of collective
sacrifices. Hence the importance of battles, defeats no less than victories, for
mobilising and unifying ethnies and nations a1ll too evident in such
sensitive areas of national conflict as Bosnia and Palestine (Renan 1882).
Memory, of course, can be easily manipulated. Witness the sudden surge
of feeling over the mosque built on the temple of Ram at Ayodhya in India,
or the post-war Israeli cult of Masada, a formerly obscure episode and half-
forgotten fortress on the Dead Sea. Besides, we need to distinguish between
genuine folk memories, and the more official, documented or excavated
records of an often heroic past (Billig 1995, ch. 2).
Despite these caveats, shared historical memories play a vital role in
modern nationalism. The question is: how far can the modernist theory of
nationalism accommodate them? There are, 1 think, two problems here. The
first is that the 'nation' which modernist theories of nationalism conceive as
the object of explanation, is divested of 'identity'. It is either conflated with
the state, to become the 'nation-state', or it is equated, as in Ernest's theory,
with a modern 'high' culture, to become a more or less stable configuration
of objective traits like language and customs in a large, anonymous,
unmediated and co-cultural unit. Now the nation does, indeed, have some
'objective' attributes like a name, a demarcated territory and a common
economy. But equally important are its more subjective properties such as a
fund of distinctive myths and memories, as well as elements of a common
mass culture. This means that we must take into account the perceptions,
sentiments and activities of its members in the definition of national identity.
The cultivation of shared memories constitutes a vital element of this
nation-defining activity (Gellner 1964, ch. 7; cf. Grosby 1991).
The second reason why modernist theories give little space to the role of
collective memories is their tendency to rely on purely structural explana-
tions. With the exception of Benedict Anderson's analysis of the re-
presentation of national images, most modernists trace the origins, rise and
course of nations and nationalism to the consequences of (uneven)
capitalism, industrialism, militarism, the bureaucratic state, or class conflict,
or combinations of these. Where the role of ideas is also admitted, the
origins of nationalism are ascribed to the influence of secularism, the
1Enlightenrnent and sometimes Romanticism. Only in this last movement is
there any room for a consideration of the role of collective memory, but
Romanticism is usually treated, if at all, as a secondary, even residual,
explanatory factor (Nairn 1977, ch. 2; cf. Kedourie 1960).
I think that we can overcome these limitations and build into Ernest's
framework a fuller account of the role of shared memories, if we marry his
insistence that nationalisms create nations to the ethno-symbolic resources
that they must use if they are to succeed. Take the vistas opened up by the
emerging disciplines of archaeology and history. The excavations of Great
Zimbabwe with its Elliptical Temple, of Teotihuacan on the central
Mexican plateau, and of the tomb of Tutankhamun in Egypt, created no
continuity between the modern nations of Zimbabwe, Mexico and Egypt
and 'their' presumed ancient or medieval ethnic pasts. What they did was to
suggest, in some cases establish, connections with distant and glorious
periods, or 'golden ages', of communal history, thereby extending the
collective self-imaginings and shared memories of their members back in
time through a reconstructed past, and conferring a sense of dignity and
authenticity on their citizens. It is modern citizens who need and reconstruct
an heroic ethnic past; but once reconstructed, that past exerts its own power
of definition through ancestry and shared, albeit taught, memory (Cham-
berlin 1979; Ades 1989; Gershoni and Jankowski 1986; Smith 1995a).
The 'territorialisation of memory' provides another example of the power
of shared rememberings. By this I mean the ways in which shared memories
become attached to particular terrains, and over time forge delimited
'homelands'. The term 'homeland' suggests an ancestral territory, one which
has become communalised through shared memories of collected experi-
ences. The ancestral land is the place where, in the shared memories of its
inhabitants, the great events that formed the nation took place; the place
where the heroes, saints and sages of the community from which the nation
later developed lived and worked, and the place where the forefathers and
mothers are buried. This last element is particularly important. It ties each
family to the homeland through memories of the last resting-places of their
ancestors, and it sanctifies the homeland by creating its sacred sites and
Popular pilgrimages (Smith 1986, ch. 8 and 1996).
Memory, then, is bound to place, a special place, a homeland. It is also
crucial to identity. In fact, one might almost say: no memory, no identity;
no identity, no nation. That is why nationalists must rediscover and
appropriate shared memories of the past. Identification with a past is the
key to creating the nation, because only by 'remembering the past' can a
Collective identity come into being. The very act of remembering together,
of commemorating some event or hero, creates a bond between citizens
whose self-interest often brings them into conflict. Hence the constant need
to reawaken public memories, to engage in commemorative rites and
remembrance ceremonies, especially for those who gave their lives for the
community; and to tie those memories to the homeland through daily
routines and 'flagging' (Billig 1995, chs. 3-4).
Collective memories, then, are active components in the creation and
reproduction of nations. Whether they are familial and unmediated, as often
occurs in sub-Saharan Africa, or mediated and public, a construct of elites
enacted in rites and ceremonies, and recalled in epics and chronicles, flags
and anthems, shared memories are necessary for the formation of nations.
States may be established without recourse to memory and remembering.
But nations require shared memories to give their often heterogenous
citizenry a common habitat, a source of pride and dignity, and a common
destiny. Indeed, if we define the nation as a named human population sharing
an historic territory, common myths and memories, a mass, public culture, a
common economy and common legal rights and duties for all members, shared
memories are required by definition. Without them, the subjective element,
the sense of being part of a nation, would be absent. There 'could be no
passionate identification by individual citizens with a particular 'nation',
only a generalised calculating loyalty to the state (Mazrui 1985; Smith 1991,
ch. 1; cf. Viroli 1995).
We can go further. If the modern nation is, in large part, a creation of
nationalism, as Ernest argued, then there are three vital elements of the
nation which, in my view, depend on the role of collective memory. The first
is the drive for regeneration which is based on memories of a golden age, or
golden ages. This is the idealised former age of great splendour, power and
glory, intellectual or artistic creativity, or religiosity and sanctity. It is the
age of the community's exemplars - its saints and sages, poets and heroes,
artists and explorers - the ideal against which to measure the present,
usually lamentable, state of the nation, and spur to emulation for
successive generations. The memory of the golden age signifies the
possibility and hope of national regeneration.
A second element is the sense of collective mission and national destiny.
There is no nationalism, and few present-day nations, that do not proclaim
some special mission and unique destiny. But a sense of collective mission
presupposes shared memories of a past or pasts in which the nation was
entrusted with that mission, and which shaped a unique community as the
vehicle for the development and reproduction of 'irreplaceable culture
values'. Similarly, a sense of national destiny presupposes a well remem-
bered past, a history of a unique trajectory along which 'we' are destined to
travel. Without such memories, without rituals of commemoration, the
nation would have no distinctive task or future, and hence no raison d'itre
(see Weber 1947; Smith 1992).
The third vital component is a sense of national authenticity, and this
400 is closely bound up with shared memories. What is or is not mine,
,What is or is not distinctive, representative, or original, is closely tied to
questions of remembering and forgetting. What is 'inauthentic' is, in part,
,What is alien to popular consciousness and folk memory. What is original
and 'ours' is that which has been hallowed by the shared memories of 'the
people'. The acceptance of the Kalevala as Finland's national epic owed
much to the survival and resonance among the peasants of the Kasrelian
folk ballads on which Elias Lonnrot based his modern compilation, even if
the ,memories' contained in that epic were less than historical (Branch
1985, Introduction).
Together, these nationalist concepts of regeneration and the golden age,
mission and destiny, authenticity and folk culture, all presuppose the
influence of shared memories of a collective past, however distorted or
dimly remembered. And, since it is nationalism that largely creates the
modem nation, the modern nation must be built on shared memories of
some past or pasts which can mobilise and unite its members.
Conclusion
Nihil ex nihilo. Nothing comes from nothing. Ernest called himself a
'creationist', but he attributed the sudden birth of nationalist humanity to a
process, the process of modernisation which, like the biblical creation
process of 6,000 years ago, was sudden and discontinuous. And modernisa-
tion keeps bringing nations into being, suddenly, explosively.
My view, on the contrary, Ernest termed 'evolutionist', indeed 'primordi-
alist'. I hope I have made it clear that I, in no sense, subscribe to any of the
forms of 'primordialism'. Nations are modern, as is nationalism, even when
their members think they are very old and even when they are in part
created out of pre-modern cultures and memories. They have not been there
all the time. it is possible that something like modern nations emerged here
and there in the ancient and medieval worlds. That is at least an open
question, requiring more research. But, in general, nations are modern.
Can my position be called 'evolutionist' in opposition to Ernest's
creationism'? Not in any strong sense of that term. There is too much
discontinuity and change between pre-modern and modern communities to
warrant the conclusion that modern nations are the product of slow,
gradual, incremental growth from rude beginnings. But, in a weaker sense,
there is considerable evidence that modern nations are connected with
earlier ethnic categories and communities and created out of preexisting
origin myths, ethnic cultures and shared memories; and that those nations
with a vivid, widespread sense of an ethnic past, are likely to be more
unified and distinctive than those which lack that sense (see Armstrong
1982; Smith 1986).
It is important to stress here that pre-modern ethnies are not nations,
whether in Ernest's definition of the nation, or mine. They generally lack a
clearly demarcated territory which their members occupy, equal legal rights
and duties for all members, and a public, mass culture. What they do have,
and what they bequeath, albeit selectively, to modern nations, is a fund of
myths, symbols, values and shared memories, some distinctive customs and
traditions, a general location, and sometimes a proper name. Without these
shared memories and traditions, myths and symbols, the basis for creating a
nation is tenuous and the task herculean.
Of course, there are exceptions to the rule. Some islands, like Trinidad or
Mauritius, emptied of their original inhabitants, may gradually be forged,
not without conflict, into unified and distinctive nations through the
conscious creation or use of overarching myths and traditions, memories
and symbols. The process of ethno-genesis, after all, goes on all the time,
along with, and as part of, the creation of new nations. The same process
may also be taking place in the former Italian province, and now
independent state, of Eritrea with its two religions and nine language
groups. Nevertheless, these exceptions only go to show that the widely
accepted model of the unified and distinctive nation is derived from the
many nations with a dominant ethnic past, and that, where such a past is
lacking, the task of creating a modern nation - as opposed to a state - is
very much harder (Cliffe 1989; Eriksen 1993).
This brings me to perhaps the most fundamental difference between my
approach and that of Ernest Gellner. For Ernest, it is possible and desirable
to have a general theory of nationalism, one that derives from the postulates
of modernity. For myself, no such general theory is possible. Though I
prefer a certain kind of approach, which may be termed 'ethno-symbolist', I
feel that the differences between nationalisms across periods and continents
are too great to be embraced by a single Euclidean theory. For such a
theory can never tell us, as Ernest admitted, which are the nations-to-be and
why they have this or that distinctive character and trajectory.
At the same time, such is the force and sweep of Ernest's own theory that
nobody can fail to be convinced of the centrality and ubiquity of nations
and nationalism for the world we live in. Ernest has reveafed the sociological
foundations of our world of nations and shown us why nationalism must
remain a vital and enduring force in the contemporary world. His originality
consists in demonstrating why the link between culture and politics is so
intrinsic to the modern world and why it must generate so much passion. As
a result, Ernest was not among the many who foresaw an early supersession
of nations and nationalism, although he was more optimistic about the
diminution of its fires in affluent, democratic states. This is because he
thought that the imperatives of industrialism and mass education would in
the end override the power of shared memories of great events and ancient
or recent antagonisms. Of this I am not so sure. The past cannot be swept
away so easily.
So: to paraphrase Rousseau, a nation must have a navel, and if they have
lot got one, we must start by inventing one. And it is because nations have
na,vels, and because those navels, and the memories and traditions, myths
and symbols they represent, mean so much to the people that have them,
that we are so unlikely to see the early transcendence of nations and
nationalism.
Top
|